(from http://info.nwmissouri.edu/~rfield/274overview.html)
This course deals with the area of philosophical discussion and inquiry known as "ethics" or "moral philosophy." As these terms suggest, the primary focus of this area of inquiry is issues that arise in ethical or moral situations, situations which raise questions concerning what we ought or should do when the issue is not a matter purely of self-interest, but of right and wrong. An ethicist attempts to bring some clarity of thought to these issues: to define clearly the language that is used to discuss them, to reveal the forms of inference that underlie our reasoning about them, and to determine and justify principles that can provide guidance in resolving these issues by bringing into consistency our best thoughts and intuitions on these matters.
The Implications of Relativism: So long as the psychopath does not believe he has done anything wrong, he has indeed done nothing wrong. You have no basis to complain about his actions, even if the psychopath acted with full knowledge that you and your family objected to his actions, and that society views such actions as grossly immoral. Although you might wish to avenge his actions by harming him, if you do so your actions are no more praiseworthy (or blameworthy) than his. You may appeal to the law, but no court would be justified on a moral basis to convict or imprison the psychopath. If this is done, the actions of the court are no more praiseworthy (or blameworthy) than those of the psychopath. In fact, a legal system which would condemn the actions of the psychopath would be no better on moral grounds than one that allowed such actions, or even one that would reward the psychopath for his actions by paying him $3 million from public funds.
Cultural Relativism
The Situation: There is a country, Xenophobia, that contains two
cultural groups: the majoritarians and the minoritarians. The majoritarians
make up 90% of the population, the minoritarians the remaining 10%. There
is a long history of suspicion and hatred in majoritarian culture against
the minoritarians. According to majoritarian cultural history, the
majoritarians are a culturally superior race that were the original
inhabitants of Xenophobia, and they therefore see minoritarians as inferior
and usurpers of their native lands. You are a minoritarian. The fragile
truce between the majoritarians and minoritarians disintegrates over a
murder case in which a minoritarian is charged with the assassination of a
prominent majoritarian politician. There is a quick move in the legislature
of Xenophobia to round up all minoritarians and place them in internment
camps and to suspend judicial procedures in all cases where minoritarians
are charged with crimes. The bill is quickly approved, and you and your
family are interned. Your brother was charged with a robbery some years
ago, and because the repressive law against minoritarians is retroactive,
the commander of the camp takes your brother to the firing range where he is
executed by firing squad.
The Implications of Relativism: So long as the actions taken by the majoritarians are consistent with their cultural beliefs, there is nothing wrong with their actions. You have no moral basis upon which to complain about their actions, even if the majoritarians understand that world opinion condemns their actions. You and other minoritarians might wish the world community (e.g., the United Nations) to place economic sanctions against the majoritarians, or even intervene militarily, but if it did, this action against the majoritarians would be no more praiseworthy (or blameworthy) than those of the majoritarians. Alternatively, you and other minoritarians might believe that you are justified in taking up arms against the majoritarians, if you can manage it. But an armed revolt against the majoritarians would not be just or right in any significant moral sense at all. Morally speaking, such an action would be no more meritorious than the repressive actions of the majoritarians to which you react.
One ought to do whatever is in one's own best interests.There can be considerable disagreement, of course, about what constitutes our interest. Certainly survival is something that all of us could agree upon, and there are other things that readily come to mind: economic security, health, good social relationships, etc. Ethical egoism itself does not address this issue, but it does argue that whatever conditions do constitute our personal interests are those that we have a moral obligation to pursue, regardless of the effects of this pursuit on other people.
One ought to seek to produce the greatest possible balance of good over evil, or the least possible balance of evil over good, for all who will be affected by one's actions.
I should never act except in such a way that I can also will that my maxim become a universal law.I can rationally will that the maxim "One should brush one's teeth" become a universal law, and therefore I know that it is morally permissible to act upon this maxim; I cannot rationally will, however, that the maxim "One should kill others whenever it is expedient to do so" become universal law, and therefore I know that it is morally impermissible (morally wrong) to act upon this maxim, and morally obligatory that I adopt and act on the contradictory maxim, "One should not kill."
So act as to treat humanity, whether in your own person or in that of any other, in every case as an end, never as a means only.Here we return to Kant's fundamental point: we are obligated to respect the humanity, the human worth, of others by our actions. We will be considering the meaning and significance of this formulation in class.
One ought to abide by those rules that rational moral agents would agree to observe when entering into a social relationship for their mutual benefit.